Cardinality of the continuum

  • the cardinality of ℕ is denoted by ℵ₀ (aleph naught)

  • the cardinality of ℝ is denoted by 𝖈 cardinality of the continuum

  • Cantor showed using diagonal argument that 𝖈 > ℵ₀

  • The continuum hypothesis claims that ℵ₁ = 2 ↑ ℵ₀

  • 2 ↑ ℵ₀ is the smallest cardinal number bigger than ℵ₀

  • so, there is no set whose cardinality is between that of ℤ and ℝ

  • 𝖈 = 2 ↑ ℵ₀ = ℵ₁ i.e. 𝖈 has the same cardinality as 𝓟(ℕ)

  • The continuum hypothesis is independent of ZFC; it is impossible to prove the continuum hypothesis or its negation from ZFC (provided ZFC is consistent).

Cardinality of infinity

In order to figure out the cardinality of some (possibly infinite) set, we try to find a one-to-one correspondance between that set and the set of natural numbers - such a set is enumerable if the correspondance exists.

To count a set SS is to establish a bijection function between the set SS and an initial segment Nn\mathbb{N_n} of the set of natural numbers, N\mathbb{N}; the initial segment of the set of natural numbers (excluding zero) is denoted by NnN_n.

If SNnS\simeq \mathbb{N_n}, then a set SS is countable finite and it has nn elements. If SNS\simeq \mathbb{N}, then a set SS is countably infinite.

Between 1874 and 1897, Cantor was the first to work on the task of finding a one-to-one correspondence between number infinite sets (integers, rationals, reals, etc.) and the set of natural numbers. Infinite sets that have this bijection function are countable infinite sets, those that don't (like the set of real numbers) are called uncountable infinite sets.

For example, the set of squares of natural numbers can be placed in a 1-1 correspondance with the set of natural numbers themselves:

123n149n21 \quad 2\quad 3\quad \dots\quad n \\ 1 \quad 4\quad 9\quad \dots\quad n^2

Infinite set is enumerable (denumerable, countable) if it can be placed in a one-to-one correspondance with the set of natural numbers.

To show that a set is enumerable we present a bijection function that indicates how its members, without repetitions, can be placed in an "infinite" list. That way the first element of an infinite set will be at position 1, the second at position 2, etc; each element will have its index.

The set of integers can be enumerated by listing them in the following order:

0, 1,1, 2,2, 0,\ 1, -1,\ 2, -2,\ \dots.

Also enumerable is the set of rational numbers. The way to enumerate rationals is fairly complex (criss-cross path in a matrix), so here is the starting sequance of the positive rationals only:

1,2,12,13,3,4,32,23,14,15,5,6,52,43,34,25,16,17,35,53,7,8,72,54,45,27,18,19,37,73,9,1, 2 ,\frac{1}{2}, \frac{1}{3}, 3, 4, \frac{3}{2}, \frac{2}{3}, \frac{1}{4}, \frac{1}{5}, 5, 6, \frac{5}{2}, \frac{4}{3}, \frac{3}{4}, \frac{2}{5}, \frac{1}{6}, \frac{1}{7}, \frac{3}{5}, \frac{5}{3}, 7, 8, \frac{7}{2}, \frac{5}{4}, \frac{4}{5}, \frac{2}{7}, \frac{1}{8}, \frac{1}{9}, \frac{3}{7}, \frac{7}{3}, 9, \dots

1/1   1/2 → 1/3   1/4 → 1/5 ...
 ↓  ↗     ↙     ↗     ↙
2/1   2/2   2/3   2/4 ...
    ↙     ↗     ↙
3/1   3/2   3/3 ...
 ↓  ↗     ↙
4/1   4/2 ...
...

Countable set

Georg Cantor introduced the term countable set, contrasting sets that are countable with those that are uncountable. Today, countable sets form the foundation of a branch of mathematics called discrete mathematics.

A countable set is a set with the same cardinality as some subset of the set of natural numbers.

A countable set is either countably finite or countably infinite set. Whether finite or infinite, the elements of a countable set can always be counted one at a time and, although the counting may never finish, every element of the set is associated with a unique natural number.

A set SS is countable if there exists an injective function ff from SS to the set of natural numbers, N\mathbb N.

If such injective function is also surjective (and thus bijective), then the set SS is called countably infinite.

A set is countably infinite if it has one-to-one correspondence with the set of natural numbers.

Comparing sets

While the cardinality of a finite set is just the count of its elements, extending this notion to infinite sets starts by defining the notion of comparison between arbitrary, possibly infinite, sets.

A=B|A| = |B| Two sets AA and BB have the same cardinality if there's a bijection from AA to BB. Such sets are equivalent (equinumerous, equipotent, equipollent), denoted by ABA \simeq B (or ABA \sim B or ABA \approx B).

AB|A| \le |B| Cardinality of AA has cardinality less than or equal to BB if there's an injective function from AA into BB.

A<B|A| \lt |B| Cardinality of AA is strictly less than BB if there's an injective (but no bijective) function, from AA to BB.

Schröder-Bernstein theorem If AB|A| \le |B| and BA|B| \le |A| then A=B|A| = |B|

The axiom of choice is equivalent to the statement that AB|A| \le |B| and BA|B| \le |A| for every A,BA, B.

  • c=20\mathfrak{c} = 2^{\aleph_{0}}

  • 1=20\aleph_1 = 2^{\aleph_0}

  • 202^{\aleph_0}

Last updated