cardinality2
Set cardinality
Cardinality
Infinite and finite set
Set equality
Set equivalence
Enumerable and inenumerable set
Set equivalence
Two sets are equal, , iff they have identical elements, or formally, if they are subsets of each other. However, two sets are equivalent iff they have the same cardinality. Set equivalence is denoted as or . Set inequivalence is denoted as or .
To see if two sets, and , have the same cardinality, you don't need to count their elements - you can just couple their elements: pairing each element of the set with an element of a set so that every element belongs to exactly one pair, .
If no unpaired element remains, such pairing of elements from two sets is called one-to-one (1-1) or correspondence.
Bijection
Sets and are equivalent iff they have the same cardinality, that is, if there exists a bijection function, , from the elements of to those of .
Bijection is a function (and all functions are relations) that associates each element of to exactly one element of , such that all elements of are associated.
Countable set
Georg Cantor introduced the term countable set, contrasting sets that are countable with those that are uncountable. Today, countable sets form the foundation of a branch of mathematics called discrete mathematics.
A countable set is a set with the same cardinality as some subset of the set of natural numbers.
A countable set is either countably finite or countably infinite set. Whether finite or infinite, the elements of a countable set can always be counted one at a time and, although the counting may never finish, every element of the set is associated with a unique natural number.
A set is countable if there exists an injective function from to the set of natural numbers, .
If such injective function is also surjective (and thus bijective), then the set is called countably infinite.
A set is countably infinite if it has one-to-one correspondence with the set of natural numbers.
Cardinality of infinity
In order to figure out the cardinality of some (possibly infinite) set, we try to find a one-to-one correspondance between that set and the set of natural numbers - such a set is enumerable if the correspondance exists.
To count a set is to establish a bijection function between the set and an initial segment of the set of natural numbers, ; the initial segment of the set of natural numbers (excluding zero) is denoted by .
If , then a set is countable finite and it has elements. If , then a set is countably infinite.
Between 1874 and 1897, Cantor was the first to work on the task of finding a one-to-one correspondence between number infinite sets (integers, rationals, reals, etc.) and the set of natural numbers. Infinite sets that have this bijection function are countable infinite sets, those that don't (like the set of real numbers) are called uncountable infinite sets.
For example, the set of squares of natural numbers can be placed in a 1-1 correspondance with the set of natural numbers themselves:
Infinite set is enumerable (denumerable, countable) if it can be placed in a one-to-one correspondance with the set of natural numbers.
To show that a set is enumerable we present a bijection function that indicates how its members, without repetitions, can be placed in an "infinite" list. That way the first element of an infinite set will be at position 1, the second at position 2, etc; each element will have its index.
The set of integers can be enumerated by listing them in the following order:
.
Also enumerable is the set of rational numbers. The way to enumerate rationals is fairly complex (criss-cross path in a matrix), so here is the starting sequance of the positive rationals only:
Comparing sets
While the cardinality of a finite set is just the count of its elements, extending this notion to infinite sets starts by defining the notion of comparison between arbitrary, possibly infinite, sets.
Two sets and have the same cardinality if there's a bijection from to . Such sets are equivalent (equinumerous, equipotent, equipollent), denoted by (or or ).
Cardinality of has cardinality less than or equal to if there's an injective function from into .
Cardinality of is strictly less than if there's an injective (but no bijective) function, from to .
Schröder–Bernstein theorem If and then
The axiom of choice is equivalent to the statement that and for every .
Equivalence
The study of cardinality is often called equinumerosity (equalness-of-number); the terms equipollence (equalness-of-strength) and equipotence (equalness-of-power) are also used.
The statement that two sets are equinumerous is denoted: or or .
Equinumerosity has the characteristic properties of an equivalence relation i.e. reflexivity, symmetry and transitivity.
Reflexivity Given a set A, the identity function on A is a bijection from A to itself, showing that every set A is equinumerous to itself: A ~ A.
Symmetry For every bijection between two sets A and B there exists an inverse function which is a bijection between B and A, implying that if a set A is equinumerous to a set B then B is also equinumerous to A: A ~ B implies B ~ A.
Transitivity Given three sets A, B and C with two bijections f : A → B and g : B → C, the composition g ∘ f of these bijections is a bijection from A to C, so if A and B are equinumerous and B and C are equinumerous then A and C are equinumerous: A ~ B and B ~ C together imply A ~ C.
Cardinal numbers
Cardinal numbers
Apart from the functional definition (given above), another way to define cardinality is to define it as a specific object.
The relation of having the same cardinality is called equinumerosity, and this is an equivalence relation on the class of all sets.
The equivalence class of a set A under this relation then consists of all those sets which have the same cardinality as A.
There are two ways to define the cardinality of a set:
The cardinality of a set A is defined as its equivalence class under equinumerosity.
A representative set is designated for each equivalence class. The most common choice is the initial ordinal in that class. This is usually taken as the definition of cardinal number in axiomatic set theory.
Assuming axiom of choice (AC), the cardinalities of the infinite sets are denoted
For each ordinal is the least cardinal number greater than .
Last updated
Was this helpful?